Worlds Within Worlds
- The Holarchy of Life
(Chapter 4)
by Andrew P. Smith, Oct 24, 2005
(Posted here: Sunday, May 27, 2007)
4. THE MIND'S EYE
"The great difference between animal
societies and human societies is that in the former, the
individual organism is governed exclusively from within itself,
by the instincts...On the other hand, human societies present a
new phenomenon of a specific nature, which consists in the fact
that certain ways of acting are imposed, or at least suggested
from outside the individual and are added on to his own nature."
-Emile Durkheim
1
"I never say that people want to act
communicatively, but that they have to."
-Jurgen Habermas
2
Beginning with atoms, we have now traversed
two entire levels of existence: the first level took us to
cells, the second to organisms. Just as atoms are the
fundamental or zero-dimensional stage on the physical level, and
cells the fundamental stage on the biological level, organisms
are the fundamental stage on a still higher level, which we can
define as the mental level.
Properties of Organisms: Physical, Biological
and Mental
Just as cells have many properties not
possessed by atoms, organisms have many properties not exhibited
by cells. However, all of these properties, like those of cells
and atoms, can still be understood in terms of the four basic
properties described earlier: assimilation, adaptation,
communication and reproduction. All of the very complex and
sophisticated properties of organisms, including ourselves, can
be understood as some specific manifestation of these
properties.
As fundamental holons on the mental level of
existence, organisms contain within them holons representing the
two lower levels, the physical and the biological. Thus all of
their fundamental properties have a physical aspect and a
biological aspect, as well as, sometimes, a mental aspect. It's
the presence of this additional level or levels that provides
the emergent aspect of each property of the organism.
To appreciate this, let's consider the
process of assimilation, in which the organism ingests food,
which is transformed to provide energy and substances to sustain
itself. The physical aspects of assimilation are all those which
take place within cells. Large, complex molecules are degraded
by a series of chemical reactions; as a result of this
degradation, energy released by the breaking of chemical bonds
becomes available for synthetic reactions, all of which occur
within the cell. Assimilation in this respect is essentially
identical to the process as it occurs in single-celled
organisms. The nature of the molecules ingested into the cell
may differ, as may some of the chemical reactions, but from a
holarchical point of view, the same kinds of holons are
involved.
The biological aspects of assimilation by
organisms, in contrast, are those that require the coordinated
interaction of many cells and multicellular stages. These
include ingestion of food into the mouth; digestive processes
there and in the gastrointestinal tract; and transport of the
nutrient products through the bloodstream to other cells of the
body.
The processes I have just described are
familiar to most people. The important point, though, is that
every process in the organism has this dual set of aspects to
it. There are the physical aspects, which are very much the same
as those that occur in individual cells; and there are the
biological aspects, which involve multicellular holons, and
which provide the process with its emergent properties.
In addition, some processes in the organism
bring into play a third level of existence, the mental. Consider
communication, as, for example, when one organism exhibits some
display of behavior that functions as a signal to another
organism of the same species (Tinbergen 1976). In order for an
organism to communicate in this manner, its nervous system must
send signals to certain muscles, resulting in a coordinated
series of contractions as it moves in space and time. This
nervous transmission is mediated by specific chemical
substances, called neurotransmitters, which are released by the
electrical activity of the nerves; upon binding to special
molecules called receptors on the muscle surface, they induce
contractions in the latter.
On the physical level, then, communication
takes place between the neurotransmitter molecules and their
receptors. (It also occurs at other points in the nervous
pathway, but for the sake of simplicity I will just consider the
interaction at the muscle). This communication is just like that
occurring between atoms or molecules that we saw in Chapter 2.
On the biological level, communication takes place between the
nerve cell and the muscle cell. This communication involves a
very large number of physical level communications, which
moreover take place in a certain pattern of both space and time.
And finally, on the mental level, communication occurs between
the two organisms. One organism exhibits a pattern of behavior,
and the second organism in some manner recognizes and responds
to it. Just as the biological aspect of communication involves a
large number of physical-level events over space and time, so
the mental aspect of communication involves a large number of
biological-level events that occur over space and time.
Notice also that not only does a process on
one level of existence include the process on the lower, but
also is analogous to the lower. The biological communication of
neurons with neurons or neurons with muscles involves
hetarchical interactions between holons on the same stage of
existence, just as the physical communication between atoms or
molecules does. Likewise, the mental or behavioral communication
between organisms involves interactions between holons on the
same stage of the mental level.
Reproduction of Organisms
Like the other processes of organisms,
reproduction also occurs on multiple levels. As every beginning
student of biology knows, almost all multicellular organisms
reproduce sexually. Special reproductive cells, known as
gametes, undergo a process called meiosis in which the genetic
material, packaged in chromosomes, is divided into half, with
each half going to one of two daughter cells. During sexual
reproduction, one gamete from a male organism fuses with one
gamete from a female, to form a fertilized cell, or zygote,
which contains the original number of chromosomes. This cell
then develops into a new organism through numerous rounds of
cell division, and various differentiation processes.
The reproductive process can therefore be
divided into four steps. In the first step, meiosis, the cell
divides its contents, including genetic material, in half,
forming gametes. In the second step, the two gametes fuse, to
form a new cell with the full complement of genetic material. In
the third step, the new cell begins a long series of divisions,
creating many daughter cells. Finally, these cells differentiate
into different types, allowing them to form the various tissues
of the organism.
The relationship between reproduction in
organisms and that of cells is more complex than the
relationships of other processes at these two levels of
existence. The first three steps described above can be
considered aspects of cell reproduction, since all of them
occur, or can occur, in the process of reproduction of
individual cells. However, only one of these three steps, fusion
of gametes, has a clear higher-level analog, which is simply
sexual activity, or copulation, between male and female
organisms. Their is no higher level analog of meiosis, nor of
cell division.
On the other hand, the last step,
differentiation, is not a component of the reproductive process
of individual cells, and it has no true lower-level analog. As
we saw in the previous chapter, the process of differentiation
requires translation, or expression, of the information in the
genome. This kind of expression does not occur in the
reproduction of individual cells.
So reproduction of cells and reproduction of
organisms are, in some respects, not highly analogous processes.
Their unusual relationship has some possible implications for
our understanding of our future evoution, which I will consider
later in this book. However, in one vital respect, the two
processes are highly analogous, and this is in the way that they
make use of information.
In Chapter 3, we saw that reproduction of
cells involves transcription of information in the genome. This
information codes for, or specifies, the amino acid sequences of
all the proteins in the cell, and thus enables the cell to make
a copy of itself. In the organism, an analogous informational
holon exists: the brain. Just as the genome contains all the
information needed to specify the functions of the cell, the
brain contains all the information needed to specify the
functions of the organism. These functions are embodied in the
activity of the large internal organs--the heart, the lungs, the
gastrointestinal tract, and so forth; the voluntary or skeletal
muscles; and the organs of sensation that mediate sight, sound,
smell, taste and touch. All of these tissues and organs are
regulated by the brain, in the form of patterns of nervous
activity. The brain, for example, tells the heart how fast to
beat; the lungs how much air to take in and expire; the
gastrointestinal tract how to digest food; the muscles when to
contract and how much; and so forth.
The brain is therefore the analog, in the
organism, of the genome in the cell; and the organs and tissues
it regulates are the analog of enzymes
3.
Just as the genome contains all the information necessary to
make a physical copy of the cell, the brain contains all the
information necessary to make a biological copy of the
organism. The physical structure of the organism, as we have
seen earlier, is specified largely by the genome: the kinds and
arrangements of cells in various tissues. But the biological
aspects of the organism, which we saw emerge at this level in
the processes of assimilation, adaptation and communication, are
specified by the brain.
The Origins of Sociality
In Chapter 3 we saw that the genome in the
cell actually plays a dual role. It directs reproduction of the
cell by a process of transcription, in which all its
information, which constitutes its deep structure, is copied. In
this way, the genome actualizes all the physical stages. On the
other hand, the genome is also translated, or expressed, in
different ways in different cells. That portion of its
information which is expressed in any one cell at any one time
constitutes its surface structure, and enables it to contribute
to the formation of higher biological stages, culminating in the
organism.
The brain plays an analogous dual role. Its
total informational content, represented in its relatively
gross, hard-wired anatomy, is its deep structure. This
information is copied during the process of reproduction, and
allows all the lower biological stages to be actualized in the
new organism. As I just pointed out, this actualization is
accomplished by the regulation of the activities of all the
other major organs in the body.
In addition, however, the brain contains the
potential to create still higher stages of existence on the
mental level. This occurs through translation or expression of
different portions of this information in different organisms,
or in the same organism at different times. This information
constitutes the surface structure of the brain, and the higher
stages of mental existence it helps to create are various kinds
of animal and human social organizations.
Before discussing these stages further, I
want to point out that only certain types of organisms form
social groups, just as we saw earlier, only certain types of
atoms form molecules, and only certain types of cells form
organisms. There are inert, non-reactive atoms that have an
autonomous existence outside of cells, and there are reactive
atoms that form the molecules found within cells. There are
non-interactive cells (prokaryotes) that lead an autonomous life
outside of organisms, and there are interactive cells
(eukaryotes) that associate into organisms. The same fundamental
distinction occurs within organisms. There are non-social
organisms that live outside of groups, and social organisms that
form groups. This division is approximated by, though is not
quite identical to, the well-known division of animals into
vertebrates and invertebrates. Most of the higher
vertebrates are social organisms, and most invertebrates are
not. Though there are some significant exceptions to this
generalization, such as the social insects, social organizations
formed by the higher vertebrates are more complex than those
formed by invertebrates.
In Chapter 3, we saw that a major difference
between interactive cells, the eukaryotes, and non-interactive
cells, the prokaryotes, is that in the former, the genome is
much larger. A larger genome can code for a larger number of
proteins, which in turn creates a greater variety of
communicative or hetarchical interactions between cells. These
interactions are what enable cells to form higher, multicellular
stages, culminating in the emergence of organisms.
The same relationship is apparent on the
mental level of existence. The higher vertebrates have larger
brains than lower vertebrates and invertebrates, and these
larger brains create more possibilities for communication. The
more sophisticated the forms of communication between organisms,
the more complex forms of social organization can emerge.
So it is that we see a fairly strong
correlation between the degree of intelligence of organisms and
their degree of social organization. Human beings, the most
intelligent, live in the most complex social groups. Lower
primates, such as apes and many species of monkeys, are next on
the scale in both respects. Non-primate mammals live in still
less complex groups or just families. The social organization of
the lowest vertebrates, reptiles, amphibians and fishes, is
generally least.
In the case of our own species, the amount of
information expressed in societies is immense. These societies
now include, of course, not simply an astronomical number of
human interactions, but a stupendous amount of information in
the form of technologies, printed material, electronic
information, and so on. Though the amount of information that
can be stored in the human brain is vast, with all its billions
of synaptic connections between neurons, it constitutes no more
than a tiny portion of this social information.
In Chapter 3 we saw that the genome faced a
similar problem in storing the information needed to express a
complete organism. If every position of every cell in any
organism had to be specified by even just one separate bit of
information, there would not be room in any cell for all the
information required. The genome, however, compresses this
information, storing only enough to specify a relatively few
basic cell types and the rules of their interaction.
In the same manner, the human brain
compresses the information needed to elaborate the most complex
human societies. Though the brain of any one person does not
specify all the interactions possible among different human
beings, let alone all the information that has arisen from such
interactions, it stores enough information, in the form of
certain rules about human interactions, to enable a large,
complex society to emerge. Thus a very small number of human
beings--probably as few as one male and one female--could
colonize another planet and eventually create complex societies
much like those on earth. They would require certain natural
resources for food and energy; and they would require a certain
amount of external information to create a level of technology
similar to that we have on earth today. But much of the
complexity of modern civilization could be created simply from
the information compressed in our brains.
Emergent Properties of Animal Societies:
Dimensions of Experience
Most types of human and animal social
organization are thus created through hetarchical, or
communicative, interactions between organisms. As shown in
Table 4
, these stages are represented by
groups such as families, tribes, and various kinds of societies.
As with the higher stages on the physical and biological levels,
there is some arbitrariness in this classification. Clearly,
however, there are several higher stages, with each stage
composed of the holons below it. Thus a family is a group of
several people; a tribe a group of families; societies were
originally composed of tribes, and so forth.
The social organizations listed in Table 4
include not only human but also animal societies, that is,
organizations composed of several or more members of a single
species. Most animal societies are no more complex than the
simplest human ones, consisting of families or relatively small
groups of organisms of the same species. Most of the higher
vertebrates have a family organization, and in some vertebrates,
particularly non-human primates, families are organized into
still larger social groups. So non-human societies, in the
holarchical model being developed here, extend no more than one
or two stages up in the mental level of existence.
Like social stages that we have seen on lower
levels of existence, however, animals societies do exhibit some
emergent properties. This should be evident in that even the
simplest forms of social organization--families and bands or
tribes, which are found in many species of animals and the most
primitive of our ancestors--have obvious advantages over
autonomous individuals. Families can care for the young more
effectively than one parent; even in the simplest nuclear
family, one parent can watch the young while the other forages
for food. This is a critical advantage for higher organisms,
because the larger brain that makes possible social organization
requires more time, and more attention, in order to develop and
mature. Bands or tribes extend this concept of division of labor
further, not only freeing individuals from certain tasks, but
making possible the accomplishment of other tasks--such as
hunting large game, defending against predators, and guarding
the food supply--which would be difficult or impossible for
individuals (Dunbar 1998).
Perhaps the most important example of
emergent properties in animal societies, however, are higher
forms of experience in their individual members. In Chapter 2 we
saw that higher social stages of the physical level exist in a
greater number of dimensions than their fundamental holons,
which the latter, to some extent, could participate in. In
Chapter 3, we saw that the same was true for higher biological
stages. Furthermore, cells in these stages as a result exhibit
higher forms of experience. Thus neurons in the brain can
experience the world in two, three or four dimensions, as
demonstrated by their ability to respond to various kinds of
stimuli presented to the organism.
The same principle is evident on the mental
level (seeTable
5 ). The higher invertebrates and
the lower vertebrates experience the world in three dimensions;
they can distinguish other organisms and objects in space. In
higher vertebrates, however, beginning with birds and mammals,
four-dimensional experience emerges. One line of evidence for
this is that these organisms can learn and remember, a definite
indication of an awareness of a temporal dimension. While lower
organisms (Murphey 1977; Byrne et al. 1991; DeZazzo and Tully
1995), and even some single cells (see Chapter 3), show some
ability to learn, this capacity is much more highly developed in
the higher vertebrates.
However, four-dimensional experience is
particularly well illustrated in the way these organisms
communicate, and at the same demonstrates the very close
relationship of this form of experience to the degree of social
organization they live in. As the classic studies of the Dutch
ethologist Nikolas Tinbergen demonstrated, higher vertebrates
communicate with each other through stereotyped behavior
patterns (Tinbergen 1976). A behavior pattern can be defined as
a series of movements in time of an organism in
three-dimensional space. In order for an organism to communicate
in this manner, therefore, it must be able to experience not
only three dimensions of space, but a fourth dimension of time.
It must be aware of a difference between another organism that
is motionless, and one that is moving in a specific way over a
particular period of time. The latter is a four-dimensional view
of the organism.
Significantly, these behavior patterns are
most often used in courtship rituals, nest building and raising
the young--all behavior that strengthens the family or band.
This illustrates that the behavior is emergent with this social
stage, and supports the conclusion that the organism exhibits it
by virtue of participating in this stage. The sociologist
Emile Durkheim could have been speaking of animal as well as
human behavior when he noted that "a ritual is a moment of
extremely high social density."
4
In our own species, and perhaps to some
extent in other primates (Griffin 1992; Russon et al. 1996), a
second temporal dimension emerges, and we can speak of
five-dimensional experience. In addition to being aware of
behavior patterns as they occur, we can remember them over time.
That is, we can store in our minds the previous actions of
ourselves, or of another person, and use this information as a
reference for interacting with that person in the future. The
four-dimensional behavior pattern is repeated, again and again
and again, in our thoughts. As I discussed earlier, this
property of repetition is characteristic of new dimensions.
The repetition of certain thoughts may not
seem to represent a genuinely different dimension of time. After
all, doesn't each repetition occur successively in our familiar
dimension of linear time? The answer to this is no. When
thoughts are repeated in our minds, they can occur in a
different dimension. That is, a single thought can be repeated
many times in the same moment of linear,
first-dimensional time. In order to appreciate this, however, we
will have to understand more about how the mind perceives time.
I will put off discussion of this until the next chapter.
This repetition of behavior patterns, both of
ourselves and of others, is the basic source of our identity.
We perceive ourselves and other people in terms of behavior
patterns that we have seen or experienced, and which we carry
around with us in our minds. This perpetuates their existence in
time. An identity is simply a relatively permanent view of
ourselves or of others. The importance of repetition in this
process was recognized by the sociologists Peter Berger and
Thomas Luckmann:
"All human activity is subject to
habitualization. Any activity that is repeated
frequently becomes cast into a pattern, which can then
be reproduced with an economy of effort and which,
ipso facto, is apprehended by its performer as that
pattern...institutionalization occurs when there is a
reciprocal type of habituated acts by types of actors."
5
The preceding quote also suggests, in
agreement with the entire thrust of this section, that there is
a very close relationship between our degree of awareness or
conciousness or mentality (using all these terms somewhat
loosely for now), and the degree of organization of the
societies we are members of. I will discuss this relationship
further as we go along.
Emergent Properties of Ecosystems: Diversity
and Stability
The animal societies I discussed in the
previous section are all homogeneous, that is, consisting of a
single type of species. In addition to such homogeneous
societies of organisms, however, there are an enormous number of
societies in the natural world that are heterogeneous, that is,
composed of different species. Known generally as ecosystems,
they may contain hundreds of different populations of a wide
variety of plants as well as organisms, interacting in very
intricate ways and extending over vast reaches of space and
time. The interactions among their members may involve
competition, as between two or more kinds of species which
require similar sources of food; mutualism (cooperation), when
each species has a benefit for the other; or other kinds of
relationships that are neither competitive nor cooperative.
Indeed, one ecologist, not entirely in jest, has pointed out
that the possible different kinds of interactions between just
two different species are so numerous as to form a kind of
periodic table (Cockburn 1991). So a large ecosystem, which may
contain hundeds of different organisms, is fairly complex.
Ecosystems clearly have a hierarchical
structure, and frequently a holarchical (nested hierarchical)
structure (Odum 1983; Ricklefs 1990; Perry 1994). So it appears
that we should seriously consider the possibility that they are
a higher form of life than the individual organisms that compose
them. But how much higher? This is currently a matter of some
controversy. Some ecologists view ecosystems as super-organisms,
almost a new level of existence in their own right, while others
believe that most or all of their features can be understood in
terms of the properties of their component species (Ricklefs
1990).
Earlier, I discussed several characteristics
of emergence on lower levels of existence. In order to gain a
better understanding of how ecosystems fit into the holarchical
view, we might try applying these criteria to them. The property
of stability is particularly useful, because many studies of
ecosystems have examined them from this point of view. That is,
ecologists have tested the effect on the stability of an
ecosystem of either adding or removing one or more species. As I
discussed in Chapters 2 and 3, in the holarchical stages of the
physical and mental levels of existence, removing one or a few
lower-order holons usually has little or no effect on the
higher-order holon. The function of a protein is usually not
dependent on the presence of a particular amino acid. A tissue
can survives removal of one of its cells. To the extent that an
ecosystem is a genuinely emergent, higher-order association of
its component populations, we might expect that it would in the
same manner be little perturbed by minor manipulations.
The results of these studies have not been
clear-cut, however. In some reports, elimination of a single
species or a few species from an ecosystem has had a drastic
effect. For example, removal of starfish from an intertidal
community allowed mussels, on which the starfish preyed, to
multiply and eventually force out most other species from the
community (Paine 1974). The hunting down of a few major
predators--large cats and an eagle--on the Barro Coronado Island
near Panama had a ripple effect, leading eventually to the
replacement of most species of trees (Diamond 1992). On the
other hand, the cutting down of blight-stricken chestnut trees
in the Eastern U.S. resulted in only the loss of a few species
of moths (Perry 1994).
Another controversial area in ecology is the
relationship of ecosystem size to stability. Traditionally,
ecologists have believed that the larger an ecosystem, the more
stable it is; and as we have seen, this is a typical feature of
holarchical organization on lower levels of existence.
Theoretician Robert May, however, challenged this conventional
wisdom by arguing that larger ecosystems, being more prone to
positive feedback loops, were actually less likely, not more
likely, to be stable (May 1974). This result seems paradoxical
in any simple holarchical view. However, it has been
contradicted by some studies reporting that increasing the
number of species in an ecosytem increases its stability. For
example, grasslands with numerous plant species were more
resistant to drought than those with one or a few species
(Tilman 1994). Other studies have found that resistance to
insect or parasite infestations was also enhanced by larger
numbers of plant species (Perry 1994).
Despite these apparent inconsistencies a few
principles that seem to govern the stability of ecosystems are
beginning to emerge--and they generally support the view that
these systems are higher stages of holarchical existence. Many
ecosystems have so-called keystone species, which are much more
critical to the stability of the system than the other members
(Perry 1994). The role of these species can account for why
removal of certain, but not all, species from an ecosystem may
destabilize the latter. The keystone concept is quite consistent
with the situation on lower levels of the holarchy. Thus we saw
in Chapter 2 that certain atoms are critical to the properties
of amino acids, and that certain amino acids, in turn, may be
critical to the function of an enzyme.
In contrast, many species in an ecosystem may
be not critical. In this case, ecologists refer to their
interactions with other species as redundant. For example, some
fungi can live on different species of trees, so if one species
of tree is lost in that ecosystem, the latter may be little
affected (Perry 1994). Redundancy, again is clearly a key aspect
of lower levels of existence. One amino acid in a protein may
often be replaced by another, as seen by the fact that proteins
in different species of organisms that play virtually identical
catalytic roles may have differences in some of their amino
acids (Creighton 1993). The nature of the interactions of the
first amino acid with the rest of the protein are sufficiently
general so that the second amino acid can fulfill them.
Redundant species, while not critical to an
ecosystem, probably make some contribution to its stability.
Nearly two decades ago, the ecologists Paul and Ann Ehrlich
proposed the "rivet" theory of ecoystems, in which they compared
removing species, one by one, with removing the rivets, one by
one, from some human-made structure, such as an airplane or a
building (Ehrlich and Ehrlich 1981). Removing one or a few
rivets may have no noticeable effect on the structure, but
eventually a point is reached when the structure is weakened. At
this point, while still preserving some stability, it may be
more sensitive to stress. Thus the structurally compromised
airplane, while capable of performing under normal weather
conditions, might crash during a heavy storm.
In the same way, if several or more redundant
species are removed from an ecosystem, the latter may not
immediately collapse. But if the system in the weakened state is
subjected to an unusual form of stress--a drought, for example,
or a very harsh winter, or perhaps a minor change in the numbers
of a keystone species--in its weakened state it may not be able
to survive intact. The rivet theory probably applies to other
holarchical forms of existence as well. To take the well-worn
example of a protein again, removing a few non-critical amino
acids may not affect the protein's enzymatic activity under
normal physiological conditions. This is because the amino acids
are not part of the active site of the protein, where the
catalytic process occurs. But the amino acids probably make a
contribution to the conformation (the three-dimensional shape)
of the protein, which is ultimately required for the catalytic
site to have the proper shape of its own. When these amino acids
are removed, that conformation may be less capable of
withstanding abnormal conditions, such as a high or low
concentration of salt or hydrogen ions.
Many of the factors determining whether a
species is a keystone or redundant, however, remain to be worked
out. Some recent work suggests that ecosystems with a great
number of interacting species frequently depend very heavily for
their stability on predators, while for simple ecosystems,
plants are likely to be more important (Pimm 1984). Out of such
work may come new principles that do not apply, or perhaps apply
in much more rudimentary form, on the physical and biological
(intercellular levels) of existence.
The study of ecosystems is still a relatively
new science, and experimental ecology, in which features of
ecosystems are probed by intentionally altering their
composition, is an even more recent development. This
experimentation may be made easier by the use of ecotrons, very
small, laboratory-sized systems in which the number and kinds of
species can be rigorously controlled (Naeem 1994). These studies
are vitally important, of course, because the earth is in the
process of losing large numbers of species, and no one really
knows how the human race will be ultimately affected by this
loss (Lockwood and Pimm 1994; this will be discussed further in
Chapter 13). As data from such work become available, it should
be possible to form a clearer picture of where and how
ecosystems fit into the holarchical worldview. It will be
particularly interesting, I believe, to determine whether they
have other emergent properties of the kind discussed earlier,
and also whether their component organisms participate in these
properties. Does a bird that is part of a large ecosystem, for
example, exhibit behavior that can be considered higher than
that of a similar bird that lives in a much simpler ecosystem?
A final point I want to make is that in
ecosystems are still in the process of evolving. Cells and
organisms are completed levels of existence; the relationships
of the holons within them are no longer changing in any
significant way. In contrast, ecosystems are changing, and may
evolve into new forms. This is a critical point to keep in mind
when comparing the organization of any forms of life on our
level of existence with that on lower levels, and I will return
to it later. First, though, we will consider the highest forms
of life on this level, human societies.
Emergent Properties of Human Societies
Regardless of how complex ecosystems are,
they--and animal societies composed of a single species--are
much less complex than human societies. Our societies are
clearly the highest form of life on earth today, and are quite
analogous not simply to the multicellular tissues and organs
within an organism, but to the highest biological stages--the
central nervous system. It isn't just that societies are
holarchical arrangements of organisms, just as tissues and
organs are holarchical arrangements of cells. The rules
governing their formation are very similar, involving expression
of compressed information in a particular kind of holon
associated with each level. I discussed this last point earlier.
The notion that human societies are a higher
form of life is not new. More than a century ago, Herbert
Spencer, and later Emile Durkheim, argued that societies could
be viewed as superorganisms (Ingold 1986). In the holarchical
model developed here, however, we must carefully distinguish
between fundamental and social holons. Human beings are
fundamental holons, capable of reproduction and a somewhat
autonomous existence. Societies are social holons and differ
from fundamental holons in ways that I discussed in earlier
chapters. Thus I don't regard human societies, no matter how
advanced, as analogous to organisms.
Nevertheless, human societies, like social
holons on lower levels, clearly have emergent properties not
found in their individual members. I mentioned some of these in
connection with simple animal societies. To this discussion we
can simply add the observation that human societies can not only
accomplish tasks impossible for their individual members, but
can invent previously inconceivable tasks. Human interactions
result in new ideas and new forms of technology that expand our
mental as well as our physical horizons. Societies can do this
because they have the ability to think, feel, perceive, learn,
remember, just as their individual members do.
Some might argue that mentality is a property
restricted to individual humans, and that social mentation is
little more than the sum of its individual members. The
holarchical model developed here says just the opposite. Mental
abilities are largely properties of societies; individual
human beings possess them only to the extent that they
participate in these societies. As Durkheim noted,
"collective life is not born from the individual, but it is, on
the contrary, the second which is born from the first."
6
We have seen in Chapters 2 and 3 how lower forms of existence,
atoms and cells, acquire new properties by virtue of their
association into higher, social stages in which these properties
emerge. Thus atoms that are part of larger molecules may have
some of the emergent properties of the latter, such as the
ability to ionize; likewise, cells that are part of
multicellular holons may have some emergent social properties
such as a relatively advanced degree of perception. The same
relationship, I contend, is true for the mental level.
Consider, for example, our ability to think
logically. Conventionally, we may say that the potential to
think in this way resides entirely within the individual human
brain. But logical thought is only actualized when that
individual is a member of a large, complex society, because
logic, to be validated, requires feedback. We need to be able to
compare our thought processes with those of others in order to
verify them, as well as to expand them, that is, to be exposed
to new ideas and information that our incorporated into our
intellectual capacities (Habermas 1979). So logical thought does
not simply emerge with the development of societies of a certain
degree of complexity, but is a property first and foremost of
these societies. To reiterate, because I feel it is such an
essential and misunderstood point, we have this property only
second-hand, so to speak, by accessing it through our
participation in the society.
The relationship of mentality and social
organization is strongly supported by our evolutionary history.
The ability to think logically is a relatively new development
in our species. While our ancient ancestors, by 50,000 years
ago, had essentially the same biological brain as we have, their
cognitive abilities were clearly inferior to our own (Habermas
1979). As societies became more complex, human thinking did
also. Nor is this the only mental feature associated with social
organization. Studies by developmental psychologists have shown
that not only the ability to think logically, but many other
aspects of mentality, including moral, affective and
interpersonal behavior, appear in several somewhat discrete
stages (Piaget 1977; Maslow, 1968; Loevinger 1977; Wilber 1980).
It appears that similar stages emerged during our evolution,
each of which was fairly closely correlated with the complexity
of social groups that human beings were associated with (Wilber
1981). In each case, the emergence of these properties was
possible precisely because of the higher degree of communication
among individuals.
All of our mental behavior is an example of
our ability to perceive the world in five dimensions, as I
discussed earlier. In addition to being aware of three
dimensions of space, our ability not only to perceive, but to
perpetuate behavior patterns suggests an awareness of two
dimensions of time. By virtue of carrying around this picture of
ourselves, other people, and other things more or less
permanently, we create a relatively permanent world somewhat
independent the one we are immediately aware of.
Because our mentality is derivative from that
of societies, however, it's different in some significant ways.
We saw earlier that higher social stages have a greater
stability and a longer lifetime than their component holons. In
the same way, societies are generally longer-lived than any of
their individuals; thus while the oldest human beings may live
for a little more than a century, large societies may survive
for more than a thousand years. Societies are also more stable
than their individual members, being able to survive the loss of
many individuals without losing their identity as particular
kinds of societies.
Societies in general also function on
a much broader scale of both space and time than do their
individual members. Indeed, it is precisely because of this
difference in scale that so much conflict and misunderstanding
results when an individual confronts his society. Consider, for
example, the emergence of a new idea, such as racial equality.
This idea appeared first in certain individuals, in whom it
might have taken anywhere from months to years to become
established. In contrast, this idea has taken more than a
century--from the time it became established in some
individuals--to become established in society; and even now it
still is not fully established.
Part of the discrepancy, of course, results
from the fact that the idea still is not established in all
individuals. Yet even when the idea has been established in a
great majority of individuals, there is still a lag before it
becomes effectively instutitionalized, through changes in law,
government and other aspects of society. That is, even when an
idea has taken over most individuals in a society de facto, it
may still not have been established in society. This tremendous
lag basically reflects the fact that analogous processes on the
social level take much longer than they do in individuals--and
the larger and more complex the society, the greater the
difference in scale of time.
This difference can be seen with respect to
virtually any new idea, and for a given degree of complexity of
society, the difference, that is the ratio, between the scales
of time I believe is about the same. An example of an idea that
has been established relatively rapidly in society is the use of
computers, and especially the internet. The rapid emergence of
this information in technology reflects an even more rapid
emergence within individuals. Unlike the idea of racial
equality, which probably took a period of months or years to
become accepted even by the earliest individuals, computer
technology can be adopted in days or weeks. So while the
emergence within society as a whole of computer technology seems
quite rapid to all of us--well within our lifetimes--it does
reflect a process that is far slower than the analogous process
as it has occurred in most individuals.
In the preceding discussion, I have purposely
used as examples of social ideas ones that are very similar to
the way they appear in individuals; this makes it easier for us
to understand them. But one must not be led into believing that
mental activity in society is simply the sum of that activity in
its individual members. Social ideas can be quite complex, and
beyond the understanding of most of their members. I would
argue, for example, that many if not most new theories by
thinkers such as scientists and philosophers represent ideas
that have already, in effect, been formulated and solved by
society. All the pieces of the puzzle, so to speak, are out
there, and have already been put together in some manner by the
workings of society. Certain individuals, by virtue of their
participation in this society, then become capable of
experiencing these ideas in a form approximating the way they
are held by the society. Much of the genius of these individuals
then lies in being able to explain what they have experienced in
a way that other individual minds can understand them.
Free Will
The recognition that there are holons higher
than ourselves has important implications for our understanding
of the origins of our actions. In the holarchical view, as I
discussed earlier, higher holons exert a great deal of
constraint on their component holons. Atoms are not free to move
in all directions when bonded to other atoms. Cells in organisms
are constrained not only physically, but biologically--for
example, the decision of when to reproduce is largely out of
their control. We would expect, then, that societies would
constrain human behavior. If we gain certain things by virtue of
being members of societies, we also give up certain things.
In a sense, this is obvious, and well-known
to everyone. Societies have rules and laws that everyone must
obey; these rules constrain our physical behavior. What is much
less appreciated, however, is that societies necessarily
constrain our emotional and mental behavior as well.
Most people can easily understand the idea of
physical control. When the strings are pulled on a puppet, the
puppet moves. It's far more difficult for us to grasp the
possibility of mental control. When the strings are pulled, the
puppet wants to move; it wills to move, it
believes itself to be the mover. The inability to conceive
of this is why so many people take it for granted that we have
free will. Even hard-core scientific reductionists, whose
worldview virtually compels them to believe that everything is
determined by physical processes, go to great lengths to explain
how we can nevertheless act freely--through theories of quantum
indeterminacy, for example (see Chapter 5).
The reason why most people can't conceive of
our minds being controlled by something else is because mind is
the highest feature of existence of which we are ordinarily
aware. We can see nothing above mind; therefore, we can imagine
nothing controlling mind. When we experience ourselves desiring
to do something, willing to do something, we have to believe
that this will is ours.
A major implication of the holarchical view,
however, is that our mind not only can be subject to
control, but necessarily is, all the time. I am not
talking here about so-called brainwashing, where an individual's
mind is broken down through a process of torture and other
procedures designed to bypass certain processes that normally
maintain its integrity. I'm talking about the everyday
relationships that all human beings have with respect to their
societies. Our social organizations exist control over all
aspects of our behavior, and they do this to a large extent--in
our nominally free, democratic societies--by controlling our
desires. They affect what we desire, what we experience
ourselves as "willing" to do. And precisely because this control
is from above, we ordinarily aren't aware of it. We experience
ourselves as acting freely.
To be sure, the ability of society to
influence individual desires is limited. A higher social stage
can't shape our desires in any manner whatsoever. Just as there
are limits to what we can do physically--we can't force someone
to fly, or to run a three-minute mile, or to lift five hundred
pounds--there are limits to what any of us can desire. A society
can't easily get people to want to kill their neighbors--though
we all know it has been done. Most people, except perhaps in
extreme circumstances, have an aversion to killing. But
societies can manipulate their members fairly easily by
concentrating on desires that are already present in most of us
to some extent to begin with (Cross 1996). Desires for
possessions, comfort, stimulation, emulation can be channelled
into certain areas, focussed on certain products, made to
conform to certain beliefs, in such a subtle way that the
individual believes they originated with her.
The notion that desires can be manipulated in
this way is not totally hidden from humanity, of course.
Beginning in the 1960s, much of the political left made this the
basis of their critique of capitalist society. This view was
particularly prominent in the writings of the neoMarxist
philosopher Herbert Marcuse, an icon for radical students of
this generation, who shocked academia by suggesting that
democracies were no freer than police states:
"For 'totalitarianism' is not only a
terrorist political coordination of society, but also a
non-terrorist economic-technical coordination which
operates through manipulation of needs by vested
interests...The means of mass transportation and
communication, the commodities of lodging, food and
clothing, the irresistible output of the information and
entertainment industry carry with them prescribed
attitudes and habits, certain intellectual and emotional
reactions which bind consumers more or less pleasantly
to producers and, through the latter, to the whole."
7
Marcuse's philosophical heirs today, such as
Jurgen Habermas and Noam Chomsky, express a similar sentiment in
their unequivocal opposition to social organization they believe
is directed largely by technocratic concerns (McCarthy 1978;
Habermas 1984; Chomsky 1992). In this view, science and
technology provide the rationale for all major decisions by
government and business, which increasingly determine the lives
of all of us. "Technology and science," says Habermas, "begin to
take the role of a substitute ideology for the demolished
bourgeois ideologies."
8
The radical left was a decided minority even
in its heyday of the 1960s, and is so small and quiet today as
to go virtually almost unnoticed. One reason for this, surely,
is precisely because it is so difficult to see that our own
desires are being manipulated. By definition, we enjoy
fulfilling our desires, and modern societies make this possible
as long as we go along with their definitions of what should be
desired. Marcuse himself, implications of totalitarianism
notwithstanding, admitted that modern Western states provide "a
good way of life--much better than before."
9
But a deeper problem with the left's view is that it has never
really been very clear about the source of the control (Kellner
1999). Is it social institutions themselves, beyond any one
individual's doing or accountability, or certain members of
these instititutions, the so-called "ruling class"? Certainly
the left has often stated explicitly that our social
institutions need to be changed. But it's difficult for any
political movement to focus solely on institutions, because this
suggests not only that no one is to blame--revolutionary
movements need enemies--but also that the situation may be
beyond anyone's control.
Jurgen Habermas, considered by some to be our
greatest living philosopher, doesn't think the situation is
beyond our control. Habermas, who is by no means an enemy of
science and technology, has spent much of a brilliant career
trying to show how society can be grounded in rational
communication between individuals (Habermas 1979, 1984;
Outhwaite 1994; White 1995). Much as science defines truth or
"facts" as observations of the external world shared by
different observers, Habermas argues that individuals in modern
societies can come to a consensus on what transpires in our
inner, mental world. By an intersubjective process, we share our
observations of this world to determine the truth and meaning of
our social interactions: "the condition for the truth of
statements is the potential agreement of everyone else."
10
The idea is that while science seeks one
level of knowledge, which Habermas calls the
empirical-analytical,there is a higher level, called the
hermeneutical. It’s higher in the sense that it observes the
mental world, which is higher than the physical world observed
by science. Actually, science makes use of the hermeneutical
world, too. Scientists must share their observations of the
physical world with other scientists, as well as create testable
hypotheses (Popper 1979). Both of these processes are
intersubjective, requiring that we examine our mental processes
and compare them with what others report about theirs. Without
this intersubjectivity, science would be nothing but a
descriptive process, with no attempt to find laws or rules
explaining what we see. But whereas science simply makes use of
this world to come to a consensus on events in the physical
world, Habermas argues that hermeneutics can, and must, also
understand this world: "hermeneutic consciousness remains
incomplete as long as it does not include a reflection upon the
limits of hermeneutic understanding."
11
It's this ability to reflect on our mental
operations that Habermas sees as the key to liberating
individuals from the social constraints resulting from a
science-based societey. In his view, the scientific program of
explaining, predicting and controlling the physical world is
inevitably extended to society, so that individuals and their
needs become just one more aspect of this world. The remedy for
this is to step up to a higher viewpoint, from which we see that
science is not absolute, but can be subjected to criticism,
bringing it under the control of society.
In Chapter 1 I argued that science confronts
a paradox in the form of the mind-body problem. I will discuss
this problem in detail in Chapter 5, but here we need to
understand that science's inability to understand the mind
completely in physical terms is not a problem for just one area
of science, that which studies the brain and mind. It's a
problem for all science, because all scientists use the
mind to understand the physical world. Because we don't
understand how mind is related to the brain, we don't really
understand how we can know anything about the brain, or about
any other physical or biological structure or process.
However, can Habermas' program of rational
intersubjectivity escape this paradox? Hermeneutics attempts to
learn about the mind by using the mind, but is this really
possible? Can any process completely understand itself? If we
can't understand the physical world without reference to the
mind, a higher world, can we understand the mind without
reference to a still higher world beyond that?
I further argued in Chapter 1 that what
science was missing is spirit, a level above the mental as well
as physical world. If there really is such a level, then
hermeneutic knowledge, like empirical-analytical knowledge, is
incomplete. Habermas presumes that rationality is the highest
feature of which human beings are capable. But as I will discuss
in Chapter 6, there is a great deal of evidence that this simply
is not so.
This discussion about ways of knowing may
seem dry and abstract, so let's try to put some life into it by
looking at how our assumptions about what and how we know are
directly related to the kind of social organizations we have,
and the way we lead our lives within these societies. Consider
first a science-based society, one that uses what Habermas calls
instrumental reasoning. Because science understands the world in
material terms, the primary orientation of this society is to
satisfy our material needs. These are initially the basic ones
of food, clothing and shelter, but are later extended to many
other less basic needs that are still fundamentally material in
nature.
Now many of us have needs that are not
material, such as for meaning in life. Demonstrating how these
needs arise in people was the great contribution of the
psychologist Abraham Maslow (Maslow 1943, 1968; Noble 1970). A
society based on instrumental reasoning can't readily recognize
or deal with these kinds of needs, because they aren't easily
understandable in material terms, that is, in terms of physical
and biological processes. Meaning seems to emerge at a higher
level of existence.
This is where social constraints are
revealed. It's true that a science-based society doesn't
necessarily forbid or prevent people from recognizing higher
needs, and seeking to fulfill them. But it definitely puts great
barriers in their way. A few individuals may be able to quit
their high-paying jobs for another life in which they find more
meaning. But this is often done in the face of considerable
resistance, misunderstanding or pity of their peers, and always
with the underlying presumption that if everyone did
this--if no one bought large amounts of non-basic material goods
and services--society would collapse. Western societies today
clearly and vitally depend on most people being dominated by
their material desires. This is what Marcuse meant by
"prescribed attitudes and desires."
A society based on rational, intersubjective
discourse would presumably be much more capable of recognizing
the human aspiration for meaning. Because this kind of society
is focussed on the mental world rather than the physical world,
a world where meaning actually emerges, it would encourage
people both to define what meaning is to them, and to seek it
out. Rational communication would provide individuals with the
tools to come to a consensus about such higher needs and how to
organize society so as to allow people to seek to satisfy them.
Such a society would not reject scientific materialism, but
would subject it to control through the intersubjective process.
Some of us, however, have a need for not just
meaning in the intersubjective sense, but for experiences of a
spiritual nature. Spiritual insights are transrational,
and so by definition can’t really be explained or communicated
by a rational process. So a society based on intersubjectivity
would as helpless and ill-equipped to understand and deal with
them as a science-based society is to deal with people who seek
meaning.
These needs are not rare or trivial. Polls
suggest that a large plurality of Americans have had experiences
of a higher state of consciousness (Laski 1968; Austin 1998). It
may be questioned whether these experiences are always genuine,
but as will be discussed in Chapter 6, there are ways of
evaluating this. In any case, in some individuals the need for
spirituality is so real and so strong that they turn their back
on not simply materialism but on other things that Habermas
would presumably regard as the rewards of
intersubjectivity--family, friends, creative work, society at
all levels. They do this for basically the same reason that
those before them rejected materialism; not because the
scientific worldview is wrong, but because it's incomplete.
There are hungers that this worldview does not understand, and
there are likewise hungers that a worldview based on
intersubjectivity does not satisfy. Since society does not
satisfy them, society must be rejected. The rejection is not of
society per se, but of a particular level of society.
It might be argued that intersubjective
society is free enough to tolerate such individuals. If a few
people want to withdraw from society in a retreat, no problem. I
would say this is about as true as to say that a society based
on the scientific worldview can tolerate those who reject
materialism. Yes, a few individuals can seek a spiritual
life--often with the great resistance of their family and
friends. But if large numbers of people did this, an
intersubjective society, too, would probably break down. Since
we don't have a society in Habermas' sense, we can't be sure
what it would look like, but it would surely resist people who
made decisions based on observations that can’t be communicated
through rational discourse.
So Habermas’ social vision ultimately hinges
on the premise that rationality is the highest feature of
humanity, and that rational discourse is the ultimate means by
which to organize society. To those who have never had a genuine
spiritual experience, it may be hard to understand that anything
could be higher. Even those who have had some experience of a
higher state of being may not consider it real in the same way
that we consider the world of science real, or the world of
rational discourse real. At best, they may regard it as just as
another way in which people seek meaning in their lives. But
even those who have had no direct experience with higher
consciousness should be able to understand that rationality is
limited as a means of understanding ourselves. We are not simply
rational animals but emotional ones, and our emotions affect all
of our behavior.
I think Habermas envisions a society where
people are sufficiently integrated that their emotions and their
intellect can work together, without conflict. Thus while not
denying that we all have emotional reactions to any situation,
he would presumably argue that we could nonetheless rise above
these emotions and both understand and address the situation
rationally. We would do this by using intersubjective
communication to answer, for all forms of social discourse, such
fundamental questions as "What is true?" "What do you mean?" and
"Are you sincere?" (Outhwaite 1994).
This level of integration, however--in which
the physical as well as the emotional and intellectual centers
of the brain operate in harmony--is precisely what the next
higher level of existence is all about (Ouspensky 1961). An
essential principle of holarchical development is that stages on
one level of existence don't become integrated until the
level transcending them emerges. Spirituality is not only about
realizing a higher level of existence, but
completing the lower one we ordinarily exist on.
No amount of rational discourse can correct
this situation. A great deal of evidence from cognitive
psychology, some of which I will discuss in the following
chapter, demonstrates that not only are we aware of very little
of what goes on around us, but that our brain constantly
deceives us about this. Our brain tells us that we are fully
conscious, when we are not; that we have a unified self, which
we haven't; and that we live in the now, which we don't. If we
aren't fully conscious, how can we know what is true (i.e, make
fully-informed decisions about events that affect our lives)? If
we don't have a unified self, how can we be sincere (i.e., have
any confidence that any social agreements we make at one time
will be honored at another time)? And if we don't live in the
now, how can we know what anything means (i.e., have any
confidence that we understand others?
Perhaps some of us read more into Habermas
than he himself intends. "I've never had any ambition of
sketching out a normative political theory," he says more
recently. "It's more a matter of the reconstruction of actual
conditions....The 'emancipated society' is an ideal construct
that invites misunderstanding. I'd rather speak of the idea of
the undisabled subject."
12
But from the holarchical point of view, we are always "disabled"
by the constraints of the higher stages and levels in which we
exist. We are freer than other animals and freer than humans of
earlier, less complex societies. But we are not completely free,
and can never be, as long as we exist in our ordinary state of
consciousness.
The Incompleteness of the Mental Level
The basic argument I have been making is that
the relationship between human societies and their individual
members is much like that between multicellular biological
stages and their individual cells, or between complex molecules
in the cell and their component atoms. In one important respect,
however, societies appear to be very different from higher
biological and physical stages. As we saw earlier, the latter
are incapable of independent existence outside of a higher level
of existence. Indeed, this lack of autonomy is a key difference
between such social holons and their component fundamental
holons. Yet human (and animal) societies do seem to maintain
such an autonomous existence. That is to say, there appears to
be no higher level of existence embracing all of these
societies, as cells embrace various kinds of molecules and
supermolecules, and organisms embrace tissues and organs. Why
not?
It may be that there is a higher level of
existence, but because it is higher, relative to us, we can't
see it. I will discuss this point a little later. However,
another possibility is that the postulated higher form of
existence is still in the process of evolving. Taking the lower
forms of existence as an analogy again, it's widely accepted
that there was an evolutionary period before the emergence of
cells when intermediate structures were being created--primitive
proteins or nucleic acid, for example, followed perhaps by
encapsulated structures that had some but by no means all of the
properties of modern cells (Ganti 1975; deDuve 1996; James 1998;
Schwartz 1998). Likewise, in the evolution of organisms, there
were undoubtedly transitional, tissue-like aggregations of cells
(Smith and Szathmary 1995). The evolution of these earlier forms
of life will be discussed further in the second part of this
book.
Such transitional forms are not found today,
because evolution of both the physical and biological levels of
existence is complete. The cells in the human body are not very
different from the cells of simple invertebrates (Bullock and
Horridge, 1965), and the molecules in our cells are not very
different from the molecules in yeast (Burgoyne 1988). Likewise,
the biological evolution of the human brain is generally
believed to have been completed between 100-50,000 years ago
(Avers, 1989).
In contrast, human societies are very
different now from what they were even one hundred years ago,
and are still changing. While this point seems obvious, it's
important to emphasize it, because it constitutes another reason
why we should not expect the properties of these societies to be
completely analogous to those manifested on lower levels. A
major focus of this book is to explore the degree to which
properties on a lower level of existence are analogous to those
of a higher level. While many analogies have been identified,
there are numerous places where these analogies seem to break
down, and these examples tend to be used by critics of the
holarchical view, those who deny that it has significant meaning
or practicality. I have already suggested that one reason
analogies seem to fail is because the distinction between stages
and levels of existence is not made, with the result that holons
are sometimes compared that should not be. Thus the idea that
human societies are a higher form of life has often been
criticized because societies seem very different from human
individuals. Understanding the distinction between fundamental
stages and social stages helps clear up this problem.
So does taking into account that human
societies have not finished evolving, whereas physical and
biological stages are complete. While our understanding of the
early evolution of cells and organisms is very sketchy, and
based largely on intelligent speculation, it seems reasonable to
presume that the transitional stages were quite different from
those that we see today. That is to say, the multicellular
holons that are present in modern organisms, in the form of
various tissues and organs, probably bear only a slight
resemblance to multicellular aggregates of cells that were the
precursors of organisms. In the same way, if a higher level of
existence should evolve, we might expect that human social
organizations within it would appear quite different from the
way they do today.
How Do We See Ourselves and Our Societies?
In addition to these two factors, there is a
third one at work that tends to obscure the analogies between
different levels of the holarchy, in general, and to make human
societies in particular seem very different from what I regard
as equivalent stages on lower levels of existence. This is the
problem of perspective. As we saw in Chapter 2, any phenomenon
can be observed from different points of view, and depending
where in the holarchy one is it will appear differently. Thus
when a bond is formed between an atom and a molecule, the
process can be seen as one of assimilation, communication or
adaptation, depending on whether the viewer is the molecule, the
atom, or the electrons being shared in the process.
This rule of perspective is relevant to our
understanding of human societies in two ways. First, our own
view of any part of the holarchy, like that of any other holon,
is necessarily partial and incomplete. As holons on a particular
level of the hierarchy, we can't see all the other holons in the
same way. Holons on the physical level of existence look
different to us from holons on the biological level, which in
turn appear different from holons on the mental level, not just
because they 'are' different, but because our point of view is
different. The physical world is two levels below us, the
biological just one level below us, the mental level at or just
above us. To change our focus from one to the other we must pass
through a scale that is so immense that I have argued it is like
a complete set of dimensions, and these dimensions are not simpy
spatial but also temporal.
The rule of perspective, then, suggests that
we will view social holons on lower levels of existence as
different from our own societies. But just how will our view of
them differ? There is a well-known corollary of the rule of
perspective, which can be stated as follows: the higher a holon
is in the holarchy, the more complete or real its view of other
holons. Thus our understanding of cells or molecules is better
than their own understanding of themselves. From our position
higher in the holarchy, we can see them in a very broad context,
including their interactions with other holons on their own and
higher levels of existence. Our understanding of them is
necessarily incomplete, because. we can't experience what
molecules or cells experience (to the extent that they do). We
can't see them, in other words, as they see themselves. But our
perspective, though incomplete, is more complete than theirs.
It follows, then, that our understanding of
our own level of existence, the mental level, is less complete
than that of the physical and biological levels. The mental
level is of course much more immediate to us, because we are
imbedded in it. We experience it in a much more direct way than
we do the lower levels of existence. Nonetheless, our view of
this level is less complete, because we can be much less
objective about it; we are unable to understand it in as broad a
context as we undestand lower levels of existence.
We can, of course, see even our own behavior
somewhat objectively. We can observe it from the point of view
of a psychologist or sociologist, detached from the subjects.
This view, it should be apparent from what I said earlier, is
made possible because we to some extent participate in higher
stages of existence--our social organizations--and therefore
share in their properties. It's from the vantage point of this
higher position on the mental level that professional or even
amateur observers of human behavior operate, and this enables
them to see the individual in a somewhat more complete way than
individuals themselves can. In 'folk psychology', this is
expresssed in the idea that others can see us (though not
experience us) better than we ourselves can.
Yet while we participate in these higher
stages, we are still below them. We can't see these stages
themselves objectively. This raises the question: how exactly do
we see or experience them? This brings us to the second relevant
aspect of perspective. Another well known principle of the
holarchy is that existence on one level can't be aware of
existence on a higher level. If there is truly a higher level of
consciousness, we can't, as we ordinarily exist, be aware of it.
In Chapter 6, I will discuss the possibility of such high forms
of life, and how we can know anything at all about them.
But human social organizations, as we have
seen, don't represent a higher level of existence, but
higher stages. What, then, is our experience of them? How
exactly do we see them? This question brings us to one of the
oldest riddles in philosophy, one that I believe the holarchical
view can cast in an interesting new light.
Up, Down, Inside, Outside
The mental level of existence, by definition,
is where properties that we call mind first emerge. This is not
to say that lower levels of existence have no mental properties.
I pointed out in Chapter 3 that some kinds of cells exhibit a
primitive form of learning. In fact, the holarchical view that I
am developing in this book implies that emergent properties have
analogs at lower levels of existence, so we might expect that in
a sense no phenomenon is completely original at any level of
existence.
However, mind becomes sufficiently developed
at our level of existence to constitute a major property of
life. One of the oldest and deepest mysteries of philosophy and
science is how these mental phenomena are related to physical
and biological phenomena. That is, does mind emerge from life in
the same way that we have seen life emerges from matter? Can it
be completely understood in terms of physical substance?
The answer to this question, surely, depends
to a large degree on what we mean by mind. If we define it as
certain functional properties such as the ability to think,
learn and remember--or acquire, process, store and access
information--and the like, then it may be that we can understand
mind as an emergent property of the brain. For example,
scientists are currently using procedures such as positive
emission tomography (PET) and focal magnetic resonance (fMRI) to
identify regions of the brain where certain kinds of thinking,
learning, and other mental processes occur (Magistretti 1999).
These studies, coupled with animal work identifying the
molecular and cellular processes that enable neurons to interact
with each other, may one day make it possible for us to
understand, in very great detail, what is going on in the brain
when we experience the world in various ways. We might be able
to identify, for example, exactly which cells in the brain are
active, and in what manner, for every kind of thought or other
mental process we have
13.
Furthermore, work in cognitive sciences may be able to tell us,
in some sense, how the activity of these cells is related to our
mental processes--that is, the way patterns of neuronal
connections perform certain kinds of mental operations (Crick
and Koch 1992; Churchland and Sejnowski 1992; Taylor 1999; Koch
1999).
As remarkable as these promising future
advances in the science of mind may be, however, they still fall
short of describing the connection between brain and what we
usually take as our most essential feature of mind--our direct
experience of the world. Some philosophers of mind make this
point by distinguishing between the soft problems and hard
problems of consciousness (Chalmers 1996). The soft problems
include all the functional properties that I alluded to a moment
ago. The hard problem is simply understanding our consciousness
of these processes--how we experience ourselves as all these
activities take place.
Another way to express the same distinction
is in terms of third person obervations and first person
observations. Third person observations are made by one person
of another, and are open to scientific study. For example, the
measurement of activity in different brain regions when someone
thinks certain thoughts is a third person observation. A third
person, the scientist, makes the observations and measurements
of events in the brain of the first person, the experimental
subject. What this subject actually experiences during this
experiment, however, is not open to direct observation by the
scientist. She may tell the scientist what she experienced,
describe it to the experimenter, but this description will still
not enable the scientist to observe this experience. This is the
essence of first person observation.
In the next chapter, I will discuss the hard
problem or first person aspects of consciousness. Before doing
this, though, I want to consider another important distinction
associated with mind, one that is quite often conflated with the
hard vs. soft problem, but which I believe is not quite the same
thing. This is the distintion between inner and outer
experiences. As we all know, we have conscious experience of two
kinds of worlds--an inner one of our thoughts, feelings,
memories, imagination, and so forth, and an outer one consisting
of the natural world, other people, our material creations, and
so on
14.
The mental level as I have indicated it in Figure 3 depicts
existence from the outer perspective. Organisms and various
societies of organisms are the holons on this level, as seen
from the outside. But the mental level must also somehow include
the inner point of view--the thinking, feeling and so forth that
is associated with these holons.
As I said a moment ago, the inner vs. outer
distinction is often confused with the hard vs. soft problem.
The hard problem is sometimes defined by philosophers as the one
of "inner experience". But surely the problem of "outer
experience" can be just as hard. I experience the objects of the
room I'm sitting in as "out there", but their qualities are just
as far removed from the physical and biological processes of the
brain as are the qualities associated with inner events like
thoughts and emotions. The essence of the hard problem, it seems
to me, is simply "experience". The inner and outer aspects of
this experience are something else. We might refer to them as
mind and body, respectively, with the understanding that we are
using mind in a way that is not quite the same thing as
consciousness.
Transpersonal theorist Ken Wilber, who uses
the holarchical view extensively in his writings, has suggested
that the only way to recognize and incorporate this distinction
in the holarchy is to view holons at every level or stage of
existence as having two aspects, an interior one and an exterior
one. By interior Wilber means, I think, both the functional and
experiential aspects of mentality
15.
He further argues that every level of existence also has both an
individual and social aspect; thus our social aspect is
represented in the kinds of social organizations we live in.
Putting these two dimensions together, Wilber has proposed a
four-fold or quadrant model of holarchical existence (Wilber,
1995; 1997; see Fig. 5), in which every level has four different
aspects: individual/exterior (e.g., the human body);
individual/interior (the human mind); social/exterior (human
societies); and social/interior (human culture). In his view,
none of these four aspects of any holon is higher in the
holarchy than any other; they are all equivalent, though
different, manifestations of the same level of existence.
At the outset, the reader will appreciate
that I have a different view of the social vs. individual
aspects of holons. In the holarchical model of existence that
I'm developing here, social and individual (fundamental) holons
are on the same scale, with social holons higher than the
individual holons. I have already justified this type of
organization by pointing out that social holons have emergent
properties not found in their individual components. Since the
distinction between my model and Wilber's is quite important,
however, and as I have enormous respect for Wilber's views in
general, I want to spend a little more time discussing the
assumptions Wilber made in constructing his model. As we will
see, the arguments that I will use to support elimination of the
individual vs. social distinction will later be used to
eliminate the exterior vs. interior distinction as well. The
major thrust of the following discussion, then, will be to
defend the single scale model of holarchy that I have been
developing throughout this book.
Wilber's reasoning begins with a fundamental
principle of holarchy, what might be called the law of asymmety:
"Destroy any type of holon [i.e., all
holons on any one level] and you will destroy all of the
holons above it and none of the holons [more precisely,
not all of the holons on any level] below it."
16
Thus if all cells were eliminated, all higher
forms of life such as organisms would also be eliminated, but
lower forms of life such as atoms and molecules would survive.
If all molecules were eliminated, all cells would be eliminated,
while atoms would remain.
Using this relationship, Wilber notes that it
doesn't seem to apply to certain kinds of societies. For
example, the system which geologist James Lovelock first called
Gaia (Lovelock 1979), and which is responsible for regulating
the concentration of oxygen and carbon dioxide on earth, is
composed of an immense number of bacteria, that is, prokaryotic
cells. If one eliminated all prokaryotes, clearly the Gaia
system would also be eliminated; but the converse also seems
true, or approximately so. If one eliminated the Gaia system,
almost all prokaryotes would also be eliminated. Wilber points
out that a similar symmetric relationship exists with respect to
several other social holons and their individual components,
such as the material universe, which he takes to be an immense
society of atoms, and these atoms taken individually.
This rule appears to be correct, and the
conclusion it leads to equally correct, as long as the
population of holons is relatively unorganized and
undifferentiated--in other words, a simple aggregate of
individual holons. Destroy all atoms, and you destroy all
galaxies; destroy all galaxies, and you destroy all atoms. Where
this reasoning breaks down, however, is when the social holons
are not simple aggregates of fundamental holons, but have a
complex, organized structure--in other words, when there is a
society, not just a population. I have already pointed out the
emergent properties in complex molecules, in biological tissues,
and in human societies. Such emergent properties are not found
in populations of prokaryotes (the Gaia effect could just as
easily occur, on a smaller scale, with a much smaller number of
bacteria). Furthermore, for the kinds of social holons I have
been discussing, the rule of asymmetry clearly does apply. If
all atoms were eliminated, so would be all complex molecules,
but the converse is not true. If all biological tissues were
eliminated, so would all cells, but again, the converse is not
true. And if all human beings were eliminated, all human
societies would likewise disappear, but the converse is not
true.
This conclusion ought to seem obvious, but in
Wilber's model of the holarchy, both human beings and their
societies are defined in such a way that this asmmetry is
somewhat obscured. His model actually distinguishes several
different stages of human beings, and each stage corresponds to
a different type of social organization. As I noted earlier,
there is a strong correlation between the degree of evolution of
an organism's brain and the complexity of its social
organization, and this relationship is especially clear and
dramatic in human evolution. Thus those humans with a relatively
primitive development of the neocortex live or once lived in a
tribal/village organization, while those with a higher degree of
brain development are found in our modern nation/state
societies. When individual holons and their corrresponding
social holons are defined this specifically, then elimination of
either one almost logically implies elimination of the other. If
a particular type of social organization is eliminated, we might
presume that so would be the corresponding type of human being.
Nevertheless, there are several serious
weaknesses in this approach. First, while elimination of either
the individual or the social may eliminate the other, the
relationship is still decidedly asymmetric. Elimination of all
humans of a particular type would immediately eliminate
the corresponding society. In contrast, elimination of the
society would have no immediate impact on the evolutionary level
of its members. If all nation-states broke down tomorrow, their
members would not immediately lose all rationality, all their
distinctions from lower forms of humanity (some of us would,
perhaps). Such asymmetry is even more apparent with lower forms
of human or animal organization. Break up families, and
organisms do not suddenly lose their limbic systems. Break up
tribes and people do not lose their neocortex. At these lower
levels surely, and perhaps at higher levels, the organisms might
persist indefinitely in the absence of their corresponding
social organization.
A second weakness of Wilber's quadrant model
is that it is inconsistent. If one is going to argue that highly
organized societies of human beings are not on a different level
from their members, but just represent a different aspect of the
same level, then one should also argue that the tissues and
organs within organisms (and perhaps the organisms themselves),
which are highly organized societies of cells, are in the same
way no higher than these cells, but just another aspect of
cellular existence. Or to put it another way, if one is going to
argue that particular types of human beings are associated with
particular types of societies, and that therefore elimination of
these societies logically eliminates these human beings, then
one should also argue that particular types of cells are
associated with particular types of organisms, and by
eliminating all organisms, one eliminates all these types of
cells. Pursuing this logic further, one should also argue that
particular types of molecules are associated with particular
types of cells and that therefore by eliminating cells we
eliminate these molecules. In other words, the principle of
asymmetry that Wilber uses to determine ranking in the hierarchy
is rendered useless.
Wilber does not make these arguments, because
he views all (eukaryotic) cells as comprising the same holon,
and the same for molecules. But this is not really so. As I
discussed earlier, there are important, qualitative distinctions
between the kinds of cells that make up organisms, and the kind
that live an independent existence; there are also distinctions
between the kinds of molecules that are found in cells, and
those that are not. A nerve cell in a human brain, for example,
is a very different form of life from a yeast cell--actually, I
have argued, a higher form--and is just as distinguishable from
the latter as a human member of a nation state is from a tribal
aborigine.
To conclude this lengthy but necessary
digression, I believe that Wilber's distinction between
individual and social aspects of holons is quite unnecessary.
Social organizations of holons are holons in their own right,
and can be viewed as existing on the same scale as their
individual components. Though they lack some properties of the
latter, such as autonomy and the ability to reproduce, they do
have emergent properties not found in their members, and thus
should be considered as legitimately higher forms of life.
Having established this, let's now apply the
same arguments to Wilber's other major distinction, that between
interior and exterior properties of holons. Again, Wilber's
model says, in effect, that interior or mental properties of an
organism are not a higher form of existence than the exterior or
physical/biological properties. At this point, I want to remind
the reader that while I am considering interior properties to be
mentality in only the functional sense, interior in Wilber's
sense includes both the functional and experiential aspects of
mentality. So the argument that follows is targeted only at part
of his interior qualities. Actually, it could apply as well to
the experiential aspects; however, I will not do this, but defer
discussion of them until later.
So we proceed, again, with the argument by
asymmetry. Clearly, elimination of the exterior form, the human
being or her brain, eliminates the interior form. If there are
no human beings, there is no human mind. But is the converse
also true? If there is no human mind, can there be no humans?
This is a tricky thought experiment to
perform, precisely because we don't have a very clear
understanding of what the interior properties of holons are.
While we can envision, in a theoretical way, the consequences of
removing all molecules, all cells, or all organisms from
existence, it's much harder to imagine what removing all
mentality (of a certain degree) would mean. It might seem at
first that if this could be done, all organisms experiencing
that type of mentality would also disappear. But keep in mind
that we aren't really talking about organisms, about human
beings, here--we are talking about their exterior aspects only,
which Wilber has defined as their bodies and their brains.
Viewed in this way, it's clear that human
beings could survive the loss of all mentality of a particular
type. That is, we can imagine human beings biologically
identical to ourselves who no longer have our rational form of
mentality
17.
Indeed, such people are alive today, and of course predominated
in earlier cultures.
To be sure, one might argue that human beings
at a lower stage of mentality are not really biologically
identical to us. They must have some differences in their brains
accounting for their lower mode of conscioussness, though these
differences apparently have no genetic basis (they would
presumably result from learning-dependent formation of new
connections among previously existing neurons). If we adopt this
point of view, it's true that elimination of all mentality of a
particular stage also eliminates all the corresponding exterior
forms of that stage. The exterior does depend as much on the
interior as the other way around.
However, as we saw earlier in the discussion
about individual vs. social aspects of holons, the same
reasoning can be applied as well to lower levels of the
hierarchy. For example, if all organisms were destroyed, then
all cells of the kind that exist in organisms would also be
destroyed. Thus we can see that if we want to get very specific
about the kinds of holons that form higher-order holons, we can
never use Wilber's rule of asymmetry to determine what is
higher and what is lower. This rule only works when we lump all
fundamental or zero-dimensional stages together as one class.
When we do this, destruction of all molecules spares some atoms.
Destruction of all organisms spares some cells. And likewise,
destruction of all rational consciousness spares some human
beings.
In conclusion, then, the interior aspects of
holons do appear to be higher forms of existence than their
physical and/or biological correlates. This suggests that
instead of placing interior and exterior on separate but
equivalent scales of existence, they should go together on one
scale. Thus we could place all forms of human consciousness
(magic, mythic, rational, etc.) somewhere above all the
corresponding brains or human exterior types.
But where exactly do we place them? We
already have seen that human social organizations of various
kinds can be placed above individual human beings. Do these
interior stages go above or below the exterior social stages, or
on a different scale entirely?
At this point, a simple though radical notion
fairly leaps out at us: can what we have been calling interior
aspects of individual holons be in some sense identical to what
we have been calling social aspects of the same holons? We know
there is a relationship involved, that rational consciousness is
associated with the nation state, for example, and magical
consciousness associated with tribal or village organization.
Can we go further than this and say that they are really the
same thing?
I suggest that we can, to this extent: a
particular structure of human consciousness or interiority
represents what a person sees when he looks at the highest form
of social organization to which he belongs. Thus the interior
experience of a modern human being is what results when that
person looks at the complex groups of people of which he is a
member. The interior experience of a primitive tribal villager
is what that person sees when looking at the social organization
she is imbedded in. And so on.
The apparent interior/exterior dualism of
holons, in other words, results from the different views any
holon is afforded when looking up, above its position in the
hierarchy, compared to down, below its position in the
hierarchy. When it looks upwards, at holons above itself, in
which it is embedded, it experiences an inner nature,
because it is within these higher holons. It experiences
itself as a subject--i.e., subjected to the laws
of these higher-order holons. When it looks downwards, at holons
below itself, it experiences an outer nature, because it
is outside or beyond these holons. It sees them as
objects, that is, objectively. Arthur Koestler, who
coined the world holon, understood this perfectly:
"The members of a hierarchy, like the
Roman God Janus, all have two faces, looking in opposite
directions; the face turned towards the subordinate
levels is that of a self-contained whole; the face
turned upward toward the apex, that of a dependent part.
One is the face of the master, the other the face of the
servant."
18
It might be argued that we can see the social
groups we belong to as exterior to ourself, just as we see
inanimate objects in our environment. But what we see is simply
other human beings exterior to ourself--other holons like
ourselves who share our stage of existence. What makes a group a
social organization is, of course, the relationships between its
members, and these relationships we see only in an inward sense.
We can't see relationships of groups (at least of very complex
groups) as exteriors.
Yet when we look at holons below us, we can
see relationships as exteriors. For example, when we look at our
bodies, we see the relationships between our cells--from our
vantage point, that is what tissues, organs, and bodies are.
These relationships, which as we have seen have some analogies
to the relationships among ourselves in our groups, are now
understood as exterior forms, not as an inner experience. And
likewise with molecules, atoms and so on
19.
To reiterate, what we call interior aspects
of a holon (H) are, in the view I have been developing here,
simply the holons above H, as they are experienced by H. What we
call exterior aspects of that holon are how the holons above H
experience H. Thus, just as there is no real distinction between
individual and social aspects of holons--every holon is an
individual from one point of view, but a group or society from
another point of view--so there is no real distinction between
exterior and interior aspects of holons. Every interior aspect
of a holon is, from the point of view of another holon, an
exterior aspect
20.
And vice-versa.
Thus what we call mind (interior) is the
same kind of holon we call body (or exterior)--i.e., there
are no holons that are only mind or only body. That does not
mean mind is reduced to body, first, because what we (or any
other holon) experience as mind is a different holon from what
we experience as body, and second, because there is no position
in the hierarchy from which we can see what we call mind and
what we call body in the same way. Mind always seems of a
different nature to us from body, because the holon of mind, by
definition, is always observed from a different relative
position than is body.
In conclusion, we have achieved a unification
in which interior and exterior aspects of holons, along with
individual and social aspects, can all be placed on the same
scale. Yet something is still left out. At the outset of this
argument, I emphasized that by interior properties of holons, I
was only considering the functional aspects of mentality. I have
not dealt with the experiential aspects. The reader can see for
herself that the same arguments I used to show that the
functional aspects of mind are higher than the exterior holons
they are associated with also apply to the experiential aspects.
Nevertheless, I stop short of contending that the latter belong
on the same scale. To put them there implies that conscious
experience is emergent from these holons, that it has the same
relation to them as they do to lower holons. As we will see in
the following chapter, this argument is very difficult to buy.